Whatever forces may govern human life, if they are to be recognised by man, must
betray themselves in human experience. Progress in science or religion, no less than in
morals and art, is a dramatic episode in man's career, a welcome variation in his habit
and state of mind; although this variation may often regard or propitiate things external,
adjustment to which may be important for his welfare. The importance of these external
things, as well as their existence, he can establish only by the function and utility which a
recognition of them may have in his life. The entire history of progress is a moral drama,
a tale man might unfold in a great autobiography, could his myriad heads and countless
scintillas of consciousness conspire, like the seventy Alexandrian sages, in a single version
of the truth committed to each for interpretation. What themes would prevail in such
an examination of heart? In what order and with what emphasis would they be recounted?
In which of its adventures would the human race, reviewing its whole experience, acknowledge
a progress and a gain? To answer these questions, as they may be answered
speculatively and provisionally by an individual, is the purpose of the following work.
A philosopher could hardly have a higher ambition than to make himself a mouthpiece
for the memory and judgment of his race. Yet the most casual consideration of affairs
already involves an attempt to do the same thing. Reflection is pregnant from the
beginning with all the principles of synthesis and valuation needed in the most comprehensive
criticism. So soon as man ceases to be wholly immersed in sense, he looks before
and after, he regrets and desires; and the moments in which prospect or retrospect
takes place constitute the reflective or representative part of his life, in contrast to the
unmitigated flux of sensations in which nothing ulterior is regarded. Representation, however,
can hardly remain idle and merely speculative. To the ideal function of envisaging
the absent, memory and reflection will add (since they exist and constitute a new complication
in being) the practical function of modifying the future.
Vital impulse, however,
when it is modified by reflection and veers in sympathy with judgments pronounced on
the past, is properly called reason. Man's rational life consists in those moments in which
reflection not only occurs but proves efficacious. What is absent then works in the present,
and values are imputed where they cannot be felt. Such representation is so far from
being merely speculative that its presence alone can raise bodily change to the dignity
of action. Reflection gathers experiences together and perceives their relative worth;
which is as much as to say that it expresses a new attitude of will in the presence of a
world better understood and turned to some purpose. The limits of reflection mark those
of concerted and rational action; they circumscribe the field of cumulative experience,
or, what is the same thing, of profitable living.
Thus if we use the word life in a eulogistic sense to designate the happy maintenance
against the world of some definite ideal interest, we may say with Aristotle that life is
reason in operation. The -Life of Reason- will then be a name for that part of experience
which perceives and pursues ideals -- all conduct so controlled and all sense so interpreted
as to perfect natural happiness.
Without reason, as without memory, there might still be pleasures and pains in existence.
To increase those pleasures and reduce those pains would be to introduce an improvement
into the sentient world, as if a devil suddenly died in hell or in heaven a new
angel were created. Since the beings, however, in which these values would reside, would,
by hypothesis, know nothing of one another, and since the betterment would take place
unprayed-for and unnoticed, it could hardly be called a progress; and certainly not a
progress in man, since man, without the ideal continuity given by memory and reason,
would have no moral being.
In human progress, therefore, reason is not a casual instrument,
having its sole value in its service to sense; such a betterment in sentience would
not be progress unless it were a progress in reason, and the increasing pleasure revealed
some object that could please; for without a picture of the situation from which a
heightened vitality might flow, the improvement could be neither remembered nor measured
nor desired. The Life of Reason is accordingly neither a mere means nor a mere
incident in human progress; it is the total and embodied progress itself, in which the
pleasures of sense are included in so far as they can be intelligently enjoyed and pursued.
To recount man's rational moments would be to take an inventory of all his goods;
for he is not himself (as we say with unconscious accuracy) in the others. If he ever appropriates
them in recollection or prophecy, it is only on the ground of some physical relation
which they may have to his being.
CONTENTS.
Volume II. REASON IN SOCIETY
Volume III. REASON IN RELIGION
Volume IV. REASON IN ART
Volume V. REASON IN SCIENCE
Softcover, 8¼" x 10¾", 550+ pages
Perfect-Bound